Journal Article |
File Downloads |
Abstract Views |
Last month |
3 months |
12 months |
Total |
Last month |
3 months |
12 months |
Total |
A Criticism of Healthy-years Equivalents |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
1 |
5 |
A Direct Method for Measuring Discounting and QALYs More Easily and Reliably |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
A General Result for Quantifying Beliefs |
1 |
1 |
1 |
23 |
1 |
1 |
1 |
107 |
A Personal Tribute to David Schmeidler’s Influence |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
9 |
A Simple Axiomatization of Nonadditive Expected Utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
199 |
0 |
1 |
1 |
821 |
A Simple Tool for Qualitatively Testing, Quantitatively Measuring, and Normatively Justifying Savage's Subjective Expected Utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
63 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
398 |
A Single-Stage Approach to Anscombe and Aumann's Expected Utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
62 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
292 |
A Test of Rank-Dependent Utility in the Context of Ambiguity |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
116 |
A Truth Serum for Non-Bayesians: Correcting Proper Scoring Rules for Risk Attitudes * |
0 |
0 |
5 |
59 |
0 |
1 |
11 |
205 |
A Unifying Approach to Axiomatic Non-expected Utility Theories: Correction and Comment |
0 |
0 |
0 |
71 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
204 |
A powerful tool for analyzing concave/convex utility and weighting functions |
0 |
0 |
1 |
4 |
5 |
12 |
30 |
101 |
A simple preference foundation of cumulative prospect theory with power utility |
0 |
0 |
1 |
63 |
0 |
0 |
11 |
272 |
A unified derivation of classical subjective expected utility models through cardinal utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
21 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
123 |
Additive representations on rank-ordered sets: II. The topological approach |
0 |
0 |
1 |
39 |
0 |
1 |
3 |
113 |
Aggregating imprecise or conflicting beliefs: An experimental investigation using modern ambiguity theories |
0 |
0 |
0 |
25 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
163 |
Ambiguity Attitudes in a Large Representative Sample |
1 |
2 |
12 |
65 |
1 |
2 |
24 |
204 |
An Axiomatization of Cumulative Prospect Theory |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
0 |
1 |
3 |
559 |
An Axiomatization of Cumulative Prospect Theory for Decision under Risk |
0 |
0 |
0 |
147 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
345 |
An experimental test of prospect theory for predicting choice under ambiguity |
1 |
2 |
3 |
43 |
1 |
2 |
8 |
151 |
An index of loss aversion |
2 |
4 |
9 |
271 |
3 |
7 |
27 |
985 |
Anchor Levels as a New Tool for the Theory and Measurement of Multiattribute Utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
21 |
Average Utility Maximization: A Preference Foundation |
0 |
0 |
1 |
3 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
21 |
Back to Bentham? Explorations of Experienced Utility |
2 |
5 |
14 |
108 |
7 |
14 |
46 |
404 |
Belief hedges: Measuring ambiguity for all events and all models |
0 |
0 |
2 |
6 |
0 |
0 |
10 |
21 |
Beware of black swans: Taking stock of the description–experience gap in decision under uncertainty |
1 |
2 |
6 |
60 |
1 |
2 |
8 |
139 |
Causes of ambiguity aversion: Known versus unknown preferences |
0 |
1 |
2 |
125 |
0 |
2 |
6 |
1,225 |
Characterizing QALYs by Risk Neutrality |
0 |
0 |
0 |
37 |
0 |
1 |
2 |
231 |
Characterizing Stochastically Monotone Functions by Multiattribute Utility Theory |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
283 |
Characterizing optimism and pessimism directly through comonotonicity |
0 |
0 |
0 |
47 |
1 |
1 |
1 |
151 |
Clarification of some mathematical misunderstandings about Savage's foundations of statistics, 1954 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
77 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
244 |
Comonotonic Independence: The Critical Test between Classical and Rank-Dependent Utility Theories |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
1 |
3 |
229 |
Concave/convex weighting and utility functions for risk: A new light on classical theorems |
0 |
0 |
2 |
5 |
0 |
1 |
11 |
21 |
Confidence intervals for cost/effectiveness ratios |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
28 |
Continuity of Preference Relations for Separable Topologies |
0 |
0 |
0 |
48 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
284 |
Continuous subjective expected utility with non-additive probabilities |
0 |
0 |
1 |
26 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
90 |
Convex functions on non-convex domains |
0 |
0 |
0 |
20 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
80 |
Correcting Biases in Standard Gamble and Time Tradeoff Utilities |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
4 |
Counterexamples to Segal's Measure Representation Theorem |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
84 |
Cumulative dominance and probabilistic sophistication |
0 |
0 |
0 |
22 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
113 |
Cycle-preserving extension of demand functions to new commodities |
0 |
0 |
0 |
9 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
217 |
Decision Making with Belief Functions: Compatibility and Incompatibility with the Sure-Thing Principle |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
182 |
Decision-foundations for properties of nonadditive measures: general state spaces or general outcome spaces |
0 |
0 |
0 |
13 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
63 |
Derived strengths of preference relations on coordinates |
0 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
35 |
Discounted Utility and Present Value—A Close Relation |
0 |
0 |
1 |
3 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
28 |
Dutch books: avoiding strategic and dynamic complications, and a comonotonic extension |
0 |
0 |
3 |
21 |
0 |
1 |
6 |
110 |
Dynamic Choice and NonExpected Utility |
0 |
0 |
1 |
114 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
267 |
Eliciting decision weights by adapting de Finetti’s betting-odds method to prospect theory |
0 |
0 |
0 |
41 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
146 |
Eliciting von Neumann-Morgenstern Utilities When Probabilities Are Distorted or Unknown |
1 |
1 |
11 |
82 |
2 |
4 |
29 |
272 |
Expected utility without continuity: A comment on Delbaen et al. (2011) |
0 |
0 |
1 |
15 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
77 |
Explaining Distortions in Utility Elicitation through the Rank-dependent Model for Risky Choices |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
Explaining the characteristics of the power (CRRA) utility family |
1 |
1 |
2 |
449 |
1 |
2 |
4 |
1,943 |
Folding Back in Decision Tree Analysis |
0 |
0 |
0 |
9 |
0 |
2 |
6 |
98 |
From local to global additive representation |
0 |
0 |
0 |
31 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
87 |
Group decision rules and group rationality under risk |
0 |
0 |
1 |
13 |
0 |
1 |
2 |
77 |
HYEs: Rejoinder |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
3 |
If nudge cannot be applied: a litmus test of the readers’ stance on paternalism |
0 |
0 |
0 |
11 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
56 |
Improving one’s choices by putting oneself in others’ shoes – An experimental analysis |
0 |
0 |
0 |
5 |
0 |
1 |
2 |
40 |
Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives and Revealed Group Preferences |
0 |
0 |
1 |
160 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
675 |
Jaffray’s ideas on ambiguity |
0 |
0 |
0 |
15 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
69 |
Learning in the Allais paradox |
1 |
2 |
2 |
117 |
1 |
2 |
6 |
447 |
Lessons Learned by (from?) an Economist Working in Medical Decision Making |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
MF Calculator: A Web-Based Application for Analyzing Similarity |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
10 |
Making Case-Based Decision Theory Directly Observable |
0 |
0 |
0 |
10 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
53 |
Making Descriptive Use of Prospect Theory to Improve the Prescriptive Use of Expected Utility |
2 |
3 |
6 |
27 |
4 |
7 |
16 |
164 |
Making the Anscombe-Aumann approach to ambiguity suitable for descriptive applications |
0 |
0 |
0 |
8 |
0 |
1 |
3 |
51 |
Measuring Ambiguity Attitudes for All (Natural) Events |
0 |
1 |
7 |
22 |
0 |
5 |
20 |
103 |
Measuring Discounting without Measuring Utility |
1 |
2 |
9 |
62 |
1 |
5 |
18 |
331 |
Multiattribute Utility Theory Without Expected Utility Foundations |
0 |
0 |
0 |
5 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
10 |
Nash was a first to axiomatize expected utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
28 |
Non-hyperbolic time inconsistency |
0 |
0 |
1 |
38 |
1 |
1 |
4 |
171 |
Nonmonotonic Choquet integrals |
0 |
0 |
1 |
31 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
129 |
On solving intansitivities in repeated pairwise choices |
0 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
48 |
On solving intransitivities in repeated pairwise choices |
0 |
0 |
0 |
6 |
0 |
1 |
2 |
83 |
On the Intuition of Rank-Dependent Utility |
0 |
0 |
1 |
154 |
0 |
0 |
4 |
410 |
Patients' Utilities for Cancer Treatments |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
5 |
Preference Foundations for Nonexpected Utility: A Generalized and Simplified Technique |
0 |
0 |
2 |
3 |
4 |
13 |
41 |
82 |
Preference Reversals for Ambiguity Aversion |
1 |
1 |
2 |
37 |
2 |
3 |
6 |
129 |
Prince: An improved method for measuring incentivized preferences |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
1 |
11 |
Probabilistic Insurance |
0 |
1 |
4 |
312 |
0 |
2 |
15 |
1,383 |
Process fairness and dynamic consistency |
0 |
0 |
0 |
16 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
112 |
Prospect theory for continuous distributions: A preference foundation |
0 |
0 |
1 |
23 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
150 |
Prospect-theory’s Diminishing Sensitivity Versus Economics’ Intrinsic Utility of Money: How the Introduction of the Euro can be Used to Disentangle the Two Empirically |
0 |
0 |
3 |
30 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
260 |
Random incentive systems in a dynamic choice experiment |
0 |
1 |
3 |
20 |
0 |
3 |
10 |
162 |
Reconciling introspective utility with revealed preference: Experimental arguments based on prospect theory |
0 |
0 |
3 |
121 |
0 |
1 |
10 |
363 |
Regret Theory: A Bold Alternative to the Alternatives |
1 |
2 |
4 |
21 |
1 |
3 |
8 |
101 |
Relative concave utility for risk and ambiguity |
0 |
0 |
1 |
24 |
1 |
1 |
2 |
108 |
Resolving Rabin’s paradox |
0 |
0 |
1 |
9 |
0 |
5 |
22 |
75 |
Revealed Likelihood and Knightian Uncertainty |
0 |
0 |
0 |
35 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
180 |
Risk Attitudes and Decision Weights |
0 |
0 |
2 |
423 |
0 |
1 |
8 |
1,376 |
Risk sensitivity, independence of irrelevant alternatives and continuity of bargaining solutions |
0 |
0 |
0 |
4 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
43 |
Risk, uncertainty and discrete choice models |
1 |
2 |
4 |
173 |
2 |
3 |
16 |
434 |
Savage for dummies and experts |
1 |
2 |
6 |
17 |
1 |
3 |
16 |
84 |
Savage's Axioms Usually Imply Violation of Strict Stochastic Dominance |
0 |
0 |
0 |
126 |
0 |
2 |
5 |
609 |
Social and strategic ambiguity versus betrayal aversion |
0 |
0 |
2 |
7 |
0 |
1 |
6 |
45 |
State Dependent Expected Utility for Savage's State Space |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
6 |
Subjective probabilities for state dependent continuous utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
18 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
66 |
Testing and Characterizing Properties of Nonadditive Measures through Violations of the Sure-Thing Principle |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
291 |
The Axiomatic Basis of Anticipated Utility: A Clarification |
0 |
0 |
0 |
89 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
196 |
The Comonotonic Sure-Thing Principle |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
269 |
The Data of Levy and Levy (2002) ÜProspect Theory: Much Ado About Nothing?Ý Actually Support Prospect Theory |
0 |
0 |
0 |
18 |
0 |
2 |
5 |
93 |
The Effects of Statistical Information on Risk and Ambiguity Attitudes, and on Rational Insurance Decisions |
0 |
0 |
0 |
8 |
0 |
1 |
1 |
75 |
The Invention of the Independence Condition for Preferences |
0 |
0 |
1 |
9 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
62 |
The Likelihood Method for Decision under Uncertainty |
0 |
0 |
0 |
86 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
320 |
The Midweight Method to Measure Attitudes Toward Risk and Ambiguity |
0 |
0 |
0 |
24 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
105 |
The Rich Domain of Ambiguity Explored |
1 |
1 |
1 |
2 |
2 |
3 |
4 |
17 |
The Rich Domain of Uncertainty: Source Functions and Their Experimental Implementation |
0 |
2 |
5 |
101 |
1 |
8 |
18 |
440 |
The Utility of Gambling Reconsidered |
1 |
1 |
2 |
188 |
1 |
1 |
3 |
383 |
The Zero-Condition: A Simplifying Assumption in QALY Measurement and Multiattribute Utility |
0 |
0 |
0 |
23 |
0 |
0 |
2 |
98 |
The sure-thing principle and the comonotonic sure-thing principle: An axiomatic analysis |
0 |
0 |
1 |
86 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
285 |
Time-Tradeoff Sequences for Analyzing Discounting and Time Inconsistency |
0 |
0 |
0 |
22 |
0 |
3 |
7 |
128 |
Transforming Ordinal Riskless Utility into Cardinal Risky Utility: A Comment on Chung, Glimcher, and Tymula (2019) |
0 |
0 |
1 |
1 |
0 |
0 |
7 |
7 |
Trust as a decision under ambiguity |
0 |
0 |
0 |
6 |
2 |
4 |
9 |
81 |
Unbounded Utility for Savage's “Foundations of Statistics,” and Other Models |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
12 |
Uncertainty aversion: a discussion of critical issues in health economics |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
85 |
Unstable Preferences |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
0 |
1 |
4 |
Utility in Case-Based Decision Theory |
0 |
0 |
2 |
82 |
0 |
0 |
3 |
261 |
WARP Does Not Imply SARP for More Than Two Commodities |
0 |
0 |
2 |
133 |
0 |
0 |
4 |
593 |
Total Journal Articles |
20 |
40 |
162 |
5,523 |
48 |
148 |
600 |
24,925 |